Author
PhD in International Law, Visiting Lecturer at Faculty of Law and Political Sciences, Allameh Tabataba’i University, Tehran, Iran
Abstract
The historical foundations of CLS were founded as a result of the failure of the mainstream legal scholarship at the end of the Victorian era’s optimism which was simultaneous to the beginning of the First World War. One of the characteristics of CLS, which to some extent was created as a result of the development of legal realism in the USA, is to open legal jurisprudence to other disciplines and to reject the thought that CLS is merely a philosophical discussion of the concept of law. CLS, firstly, throws a shadow of doubt on the attitude of the mainstream legal scholarship premised upon the belief that law is perfect, autonomous, and logical. In ultimately rejecting this belief, CLS shows that the so-called triumphs of the conventional legal mainstream are ambiguous. By acknowledging the risk of scepticism and by advancing its ideals according to this, CLS has provided conditions, and therefore means, for the social world to continuously reconsider itself.
Keywords
- Abel, Richard A. (1980), Redirecting Social Studies of Law, Law and Society review, Vol. 14, pp. 805-829.
- Boyle, James (1985), Modernist Social Theory: Roberto Unger’s Passion, Harvard Law Review, Vol. 98, No. 5, pp. 1066-1083.
- Boyle, James (1994), Critical Legal Studies, UK, Dartmouth Publishing Company Limited.
- Cane, Peter & Conaghan, Joanne (2008), The New Oxford Companion to Law, 1st ed., UK, Oxford University Press.
- Dupuy, Pierre Marie (2005), Some Reflection on Contemporary International Law and the Appeal to Universal Values: A Response to Martti Koskenniemi, The European Journal of International Law, Vol. 16, N. 1, pp. 131-137.
- Dworkin, Ronald (1977), Taking Rights Seriously, London, Duckworth.
- Dworkin, Ronald (1986), Law’s Empire, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
- Gordon, Robert (1989), Brendan Brown Lecture: Critical Legal Studies as a Teaching Method, Loyola Law Review, Vol. 35, No. 2, pp. 383-407.
- Hunt, Alan (1986), The Theory of Critical Legal Studies, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 6, No. 1, pp. 1-45.
- Hunt, Alan (1987), The Critique of Law: What is Critical about Critical Legal Theory, Journal of Law and Society, Vol. 14, N. 1, pp. 5-19.
- Kairys, David (1990), The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique, New York, Pantheon Books.
- Kennedy, Duncan (1991), The stakes of Law, or Hale and Foucault!, Legal Studies Forum, V. 15, pp. 327-365.
- Koskenniemi, Martti (2004), The Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and fall of International Law 1870-1960, Cambridge, UK, Cambridge University Press.
- Koskenniemi, Martti (2005), From Apology to Utopia: The Structure of Legal Argument, UK, Cambridge University Press.
- Manger, Frank & Seron, Carroll (1984), Critical Legal Studies versus Critical Legal Theory: A Comment on Method, Law & Policy, Vol. 6, No. 3, pp. 257-297.
- Peller, Gary (1985), The Metaphysics of American Law, California Law Review, Vol. 73, No. 4, pp. 1152-1190.
- Render, Harry (1982), In the Beginning was the Deed: Reflections on the Passage of Faust, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Tushnet, Mark (1991), Critical Legal Studies: A political History, Yale Law Journal, Vol. 100, pp. 1515-1544.
- Unger, Roberto Mangaberia (1984), Passion: An Essay on Personality, New York, The Free Press.
- Unger, Roberto Mangaberia (1986), The Critical Legal Studies Movement, USA, Harvard University Press.
- Walker, David M. (1980), The Oxford Companion to Law, Oxford, Clarendon Press.
- Weber, Max (1954), Max Weber on Law in Economy and Society, Edited with an introduction by Max Rheinstein, Translated by Edward Shils and Max Rheinstein Cambridge, Mass.